IntroductionWelcome to my end of Round 2. The more Alonzo and I discuss here, the less I actually think there is much of a difference between rule utilitarianism and desirism after all. However, after some reflection, I think I’ve identified four related disagreements that Alonzo and I have.
Practicality vs. NormativityThe first disagreement between us is our biggest. I want to look at Alonzo’s claim that “what is moral or immoral is […] what people generally have reason to reward/praise or punish/condemn”. Here, Alonzo does not seem to separate pragmatism (“what is effective at getting people to desire things”) from normativity (“what people morally ought to desire”), while I do. Alonzo seems to discuss “morality from a sociological standpoint” rather than a “morality from a normative standpoint”. I think morality is more than just what we are using our social tools on, but what we
ought to use our social tools to change.
Slavery and Future PeopleFor an example, consider slavery. People today generally recognize that slavery is wrong. More importantly, people today generally believe slavery was always wrong. However, there once was a time when people generally believed slavery was morally good. At that point in time, these people did not have reason to condemn slavery or reward emancipation. However, that didn’t mean slavery was morally correct at the time. These people were just mistaken about what is moral.
This can also be seen in Alonzo and my discussion about future people. Alonzo thinks that future people can only matter if people who currently exist care about future people. I, however, think that people
morally ought to care about future people, just like people morally ought to care about slaves, regardless of whether anyone currently does.
Does Desirism Hear The Strongest Needs?, RepriseThis also fits in with my general concern about impartiality from before. If practicality is the sole standard of morality, then the loudest desires win the day. Typically, this means more focus on first-world problems and less focus on issues that have much larger consequences, like developing world poverty and animal rights, because the extremely poor and nonhuman animals lack the ability to speak up to themselves, especially compared to rich and successful people. While this may be the case in reality, it
ought not be the case, and that’s an important distinction that I think Alonzo misses.
Alonzo vs. Me on Meta-EthicsThis concern is based on a different meta-ethics than the one Alonzo offers. On
my meta-ethics, when someone says something is morally right or wrong, they are invoking a particular moral standard and holding people to that. When I say we morally ought to care about future people, I’m invoking my utilitarianism and saying that people who don’t care about future people are not following my view of utilitarianism because they are not maximizing utility by being callous towards the happiness and suffering of future people.
In doing so, I’m separating what is moral from what people feel motivated to do, a view called
moral externalism. Alonzo proposes a simple theory of motivation that says people only do what is consistent with their desires. This theory may be complicated by self-defeating actions and may not be well grounded in actual psychology, but I think it is good enough for our purposes. Similarly, Newtonian physics isn’t technically correct, but it’s good enough for most physics. So I’m willing to accept this theory of motivation.
However, I don’t think what we are presently motivated to do has anything to do with what we morality ought to be motivated to do – morality. So Alonzo would be right to retort that people might not be motivated to care about future people because they may lack the desires. And Alonzo would be right to point out that in order to actually protect future people, it would be best if we worked on getting people to start having those desires. But while Alonzo is correct on both of these things, I think Alonzo is missing the point about what morality is really about.
Praise / Condemnation vs. Other Methods of Behavioral ChangeAnother disagreement is practical instead of normative. I’m concerned with putting reward, praise, punishment, and condemnation in the front-and-center – they’re not the most effective ways of achieving social change. Moralizing certainly works in some cases and guilt can be a powerful motivator. But this only works to enforce causes currently in the mainstream. Guilt may make people think more about recycling, but it doesn’t seem to do much to prevent people from eating meat or donating much of their income – two social problems I see as particularly important today from a utilitarian standpoint.
Additionally, most of the time, we seem to have an easier path to social change by offering non-moral reasons and making things easier. Recycling behaviors at my school never changed much with campaigns to shame non-recyclers or praise recyclers, but the needle did move in a big way once more recycling bins were placed around campus and the recycling bins were better labeled. Likewise, others have found that moralizing about animal welfare did little to change people’s meat-eating habits, but
discussing health benefits has.
In many cases, we might want to talk about “effectiveness” more broadly and eschew talk specifically about social tools. While talk of social tools is helpful when the sociology and evolutionary development of morality, I think social tools are just one part of a larger basket of approaches we could consider when looking to actually make behavior change happen.
Alonzo says that “[s]tandard utilitarianism treats reward and punishment as just another act to be evaluated according to its consequences [but that Desirism treats reward and punishment as central to the institution of morality”. I hope that my broadening of tools of effectiveness shows that standard utilitarianism should be preferred here.
There doesn’t seem to be any reason to single out reward and punishment as anything special when it comes to morality. Instead, we should pursue what maximizes utility. Instead, we should praise when praising maximizes utility and refrain from praising when it doesn’t; we should condemn when condemnation maximizes utility and refrain from condemnation when it doesn’t. If, for example, condemnation would only make someone feel guilty and not inspire behavior change, then it makes sense not to condemn the person and instead do something that actually would create the behavior change.
Desires vs. RulesA third disagreement Alonzo and I have is whether rules or desires should be the primary object of moral evaluation. Alonzo and I both want people to change their behavior to be more benevolent. But, practically speaking, is this goal best accomplished by getting people to change their rules, getting them to change their desires, or something else entirely?
Actually, I think this disagreement is a difficult one to resolve and I don’t think rule utilitarianism is a clear winner here. In fact, this might be an empirical question and perhaps we should try both rules-focused and desires-focused techniques and observe which one is the most effective, and then go with that. It will be awhile until we have this data, however, so I’ll tell you why rules might be better after all.
Let’s come back to the simple theory of “motivation as desires”. We can apply this analysis to New Years Resolutions, as Alonzo mentioned and note that people generally have a desire to be healthy and generally understand that regular exercise will accomplish this desire. But the desire to be healthy will typically only get people to the gym for two weeks in January, if any time at all. This is because we also have a desire to not spend too much effort, or we get caught up in the moment of other activities involving other desires, etc. Our desire to be healthy gets lost among all our other desires.
Rules can punch through this problem with desires. First, some wisdom from motivational blogs (see
here and
here) suggests that by making an action like exercise something you “must” do rather than “should” do, you’re more likely to do it. Additionally, we’ve long known
the power of precommitment, especially public precommitment, as a motivator where you declare in advance you will stick to a rule. Yes, this is pretty weak and circumstantial, but it is some preliminary evidence in favor of rules.
More importantly, rules seem more malleable than desires. I
may be speaking from only my experience, but when I sought to begin to exercise, I wasn’t able to motivate myself by meditating upon my desire to be healthy and try to amp it up – instead, I made exercise a “must” and
precommitted publicly.
I agree with Alonzo that someone won’t adopt a rule that’s contrary to their desires and it is desires that motivate when we look all the way at the bottom. No one is going to adopt a rule to exercise every Monday, Wednesday, and Friday no matter what if they don’t also have a desire to be healthy. But, as I mentioned earlier, once the desire to be healthy is in place, further praise and condemnation doesn’t seem to get people into the gym – it only makes them feel guilt.
Truth vs. UtilityThe last disagreement we have is much more minor than the other three and I put it here mostly as an appendix to be thorough. I proposed that “the best version of utilitarianism is the version that maximizes utility” whereas Alonzo thinks instead the best version of utilitarianism is the version that “contains true premises”. Alonzo says that he will “go with truth and forsake utility” if the two conflict.
Alonzo has a good point. We decide which hypothesis best explains the origin of the moon by looking at evidence, not utility. So why not do the same with which hypothesis best explains morality?
My concern is that I don’t think facts about morality work in the same way as facts about the moon. Specifically, I think there are lots of moral standards we can choose from. Each one of these successfully explains what we can and cannot do and works to guide behavior. However, we still need to choose which theory we want to personally like best. Therefore, we need desiderata for picking one theory among all the possible true theories, as truth isn’t enough to limit ourselves.
ConclusionSo where are we now?
My Critique of AlonzoI’ve renewed my argument from before that
(b) rules are more malleable than desires and now also claim that
(b2) internalizing rules are more effective at creating self-change than internalizing desires.
I still think that (c) the role of reflection in desirism is less clear, but haven’t pursued this issue as important.
I’ve dropped my concern that (d) desires may not exist, as Alonzo has successfully convinced me in his rebuttal not to worry about this.
I’ve bolstered my argument that (e) two-level utilitarianism makes it clearer impartial attitudes matter when considering what problems ought to be prioritized morally, (f) desirism has a strange attitude toward maximization and (g) desirism does not take the welfare of future people into account by making a more general argument that
(e2) desirism casts aside an important divide between normativity and practicality.I’ve added a new practical concern that
(h) desirism over-emphasizes the use of social tools relative to other methods we could pursue to create social change.Alonzo’s Critique of MeIn this round, I’ve answered Alonzo’s concerns that rules are not able to motivate people by suggesting that while desires are the ultimate motivator, it is easier to add rules to a general desire than to adopt new desires.
I’ve addressed Alonzo’s bridge between desirism and two-level utilitarianism by questioning why social tools like reward and punishment should be singled out relative to other tools for behavior change.
Lastly, I also addressed Alonzo’s question about “matters to who” by suggesting a different type of mattering – what one ought to matter, rather than actually matters.