I am delighted to join this community of online moral theorists—theorists who seem to have a deep concern that their theories impact and improve upon both their online and offline societies!
I am a senior doctoral candidate in ethical, moral, social, and political philosophy, at the University of Michigan, Ann Arbor. My curriculum vitae is here: http://goo.gl/pSuGp. My webpage is here: http://natcphd.me.
I am currently conducting research to analyse and criticise (1) classical Utilitarian and (2) contemporary Utilitarian explanations of the wrongness of Negro slavery. The output of my research will be:
(1) an article, entitled 'British Utilitarianism's justification of Negro slavery', and
(2) an article, entitled 'What is wrong with [R. M. Hare's arguments against Negro] slavery'
1. Classical Utilitarianism: Bentham & Mill
'For all their intelligence and imagination neither Bentham nor Mill seemed to recognise or discuss' the possibility that 'utilitarianism can require slavery' (Jonathan Wolff 2006: 1).
Wolff was wrong. I shall argue that these two inventors of Utilitarianism both recognised and discussed the way in which their new moral theory explained not the wrongness, but the rightness of the Negro slavery that Britain slowly abolished during their lifetime. Wolff's words are ambiguous. Wolff could mean (a) 'utilitarianism can require the introduction of slavery where slavery does not already exist' or (b) 'utilitarianism can require the maintenance of slavery where slavery already exists'. I shall show that Mill recognised and discussed (a) and that Bentham recognised and discussed (b).
Wolff, Jonathan. 2006. Making the world safe for Utilitarianism. In Political philosophy, ed. Anthony O'Hear, 1–22. Cambridge: CUP.
2. Contemporary Utilitarianism: Hare
'It is often said that utilitarianism must be an objectionable creed because it could in certain circumstances condone or even commend slavery given that circumstances can be envisaged in which utility would be maximized by preserving a slave-owning society and not abolishing slavery'.
This is how Richard Mervyn Hare (1979: 104) put the challenge that slavery poses to Utilitarianism. Hare responded by arguing that Utilitarianism can explain both (a) why our intuition that slavery is wrong is the best intuition for us to have, and (b) why our intuition that slavery is wrong is true. I shall focus on the three distinct arguments that Hare offers in support of (b):
—an argument from disutility: Slavery is wrong, because it produces misery.
—an argument from inconsistency: Slavery is wrong, because it treats unequally the equal interests of the free and the enslaved person.
—an argument from authority: Slavery is wrong, because R. M. Hare said so.
Hare, Richard Mervyn. 1979. What is wrong with slavery. Philosophy & Public Affairs 8(2): 103–121.
I would love to hear the perspectives of utilitarians on the arguments I am developing!
Nathaniel
I am a senior doctoral candidate in ethical, moral, social, and political philosophy, at the University of Michigan, Ann Arbor. My curriculum vitae is here: http://goo.gl/pSuGp. My webpage is here: http://natcphd.me.
I am currently conducting research to analyse and criticise (1) classical Utilitarian and (2) contemporary Utilitarian explanations of the wrongness of Negro slavery. The output of my research will be:
(1) an article, entitled 'British Utilitarianism's justification of Negro slavery', and
(2) an article, entitled 'What is wrong with [R. M. Hare's arguments against Negro] slavery'
1. Classical Utilitarianism: Bentham & Mill
'For all their intelligence and imagination neither Bentham nor Mill seemed to recognise or discuss' the possibility that 'utilitarianism can require slavery' (Jonathan Wolff 2006: 1).
Wolff was wrong. I shall argue that these two inventors of Utilitarianism both recognised and discussed the way in which their new moral theory explained not the wrongness, but the rightness of the Negro slavery that Britain slowly abolished during their lifetime. Wolff's words are ambiguous. Wolff could mean (a) 'utilitarianism can require the introduction of slavery where slavery does not already exist' or (b) 'utilitarianism can require the maintenance of slavery where slavery already exists'. I shall show that Mill recognised and discussed (a) and that Bentham recognised and discussed (b).
Wolff, Jonathan. 2006. Making the world safe for Utilitarianism. In Political philosophy, ed. Anthony O'Hear, 1–22. Cambridge: CUP.
2. Contemporary Utilitarianism: Hare
'It is often said that utilitarianism must be an objectionable creed because it could in certain circumstances condone or even commend slavery given that circumstances can be envisaged in which utility would be maximized by preserving a slave-owning society and not abolishing slavery'.
This is how Richard Mervyn Hare (1979: 104) put the challenge that slavery poses to Utilitarianism. Hare responded by arguing that Utilitarianism can explain both (a) why our intuition that slavery is wrong is the best intuition for us to have, and (b) why our intuition that slavery is wrong is true. I shall focus on the three distinct arguments that Hare offers in support of (b):
—an argument from disutility: Slavery is wrong, because it produces misery.
—an argument from inconsistency: Slavery is wrong, because it treats unequally the equal interests of the free and the enslaved person.
—an argument from authority: Slavery is wrong, because R. M. Hare said so.
Hare, Richard Mervyn. 1979. What is wrong with slavery. Philosophy & Public Affairs 8(2): 103–121.
I would love to hear the perspectives of utilitarians on the arguments I am developing!
Nathaniel